year2027 Posted August 6, 2008 Share Posted August 6, 2008 God first Beloved friends God loves you my dear friends reading a old book at http://ia301333.us.archive.org/3/items/the...wnuoft_djvu.txt chapter 1 below to give you a ideal about the book wrote in 18something can be downloaded at the above link or Archive.org INTRODUCTION PHILOSOPHY aims at a rational and systematic compre hension of reality. Or, since experience is the fundamental fact in all theorizing, and since reality can be known only in experience, in the largest sense of that word, we may say that philosophy aims at a rational and systematic com prehension and interpretation of experience. This aim, however, is only an ideal which is very im perfectly realized. Philosophy is militant, not triumphant. As it has required the labor of many generations to bring the system of thought to its present development, so it will require the labor of many more to bring that system to anything like completion. Meanwhile only general outlines and partial views are possible. These, however, may be valuable, if they begin with admitted facts and make good their claims as they go along. Philosophic theories fall into two great classes, theories of knowing and theories of being. This results from the nature of the case. The theory of being is the ultimate aim of philosophy, but that theory cannot be completed without a theory of knowing. A philosophic system is determined and characterized by its position on these two points. In the doctrine of knowledge, the fundamental division of theories turns upon their conception of the mind as active or passive in knowing. However complicated the theories may seem in their application, the essential question is this, Is the mind active or passive in knowledge? Perhaps we may think that the term mind smacks too much of meta physics, and then the question takes another form, Is knowing an active process determined by laws within thought itself, or is it only a mechanical reflection of objects in a passive consciousness? The answer to this question gives direction to our philosophy ; and a long train of speculative consequences depends upon it. In the doctrine of being, the deepest distinction of theories turns upon the conception of fundamental being, whether it be conceived as mechanical and unintelligent, or as purposive and intelligent. Unwittingly, often, but none the less really, philosophic debate revolves around the antitheses of freedom and necessity, of purpose and mechan ism, of intelligence and non-intelligence. In addition, as already suggested, the theories of knowing and of being mutually affect one another. There are, then, certain typical theories of knowing and of being, each of which has its peculiar implications ; and whoever would understand the problems and the history of philosophy must master these typical theories. When this is done, particular systems may be understood in their essen tial w^orth, or worthlessness, as soon as we get their relation to the typical theory. "When we know the logic of the gen eral view we need not waste time in studying its particular forms. If they are logical we know where they must come out. If they are not logical we have no system but disjointed observations. They are systems only in the catalogue or advertisement. Hence, epistemology, or the doctrine of knowledge, andmetaphysics, or the doctrine of real existence, are the two grand divisions of philosophy. As already pointed out, these do not admit of any absolute separation, as if the the ory of one could be completed without a theory of the other. They are, then, different aspects of the whole question rather than mutually independent factors. At the same time, they are sufficiently distinct to make it desirable to treat them separately. Historically, systems of philosophy have commonly em phasized one or the other of these two questions so as to be come predominantly either theories of knowing or theories of being. Thus the systems of Locke, Hume, and Kant are pre-eminently theories of knowing. The systems of Spinoza and Leibnitz" are fundamentally theories of being. In the historical development of thought, theories of being come first. This is due to the fact that the mind is objective in its first activities, and becomes reflective only at a later date. Knowledge is really determined both by the subject and by the object ; but the object is the only determinant for unre- flective thought. The full significance of the subject for knowledge was first proclaimed by Kant. Thought first goes straight to things, and if it stumbled on no contradic tions among its conceptions it would probably never suspect the existence and complexity of its own processes. In estimating, then, a philosophical system, we must get its position on these fundamental points of knowing and being. All else, so far as it is logical, results from that po sition. If we have a knowledge of the typical theories, we may spare ourselves the trouble of reading new works be yond the point necessary to determine their fundamental position. For instance, if one has mastered the logic of sen sationalism in Hume, there is no need to waste time on the pathetic efforts of later sensationalists to galvanize their dead philosophy into some semblance of life. Philosophy aims at a rational comprehension of reality. But the instrument of philosophy is thought itself. All sys tems of whatever kind, even systems of doubt and denial, must recognize the existence of laws of thought whereby the normal processes and results of thinking are distin guished from the abnormal. Without such recognition there is no distinction between rational and irrational, and naught remains but caprice, obstinacy, and infatuation. Hence the logical order of philosophical study is logic, epistemology, and metaphysics. The first treats of the laws of normal thinking, or the science of thought. The second applies these laws to the problem of knowledge, and, by analyzing the idea of knowledge, aims to discover its gen eral conditions and implications. These two are only dif ferent aspects of the one question. The third asks after the final conceptions reached by thought concerning real exist ence, or, more specifically, concerning man, nature, and the fundamental reality. We have, then, as the most significant divisions of phil osophic study the following : 1. Logic, or the Theory of Thought ; 2. Epistemology, or the Theory of Knowledge ; 3. Metaphysics, or the Theory of Being. The first two divisions will be discussed in the pres ent volume. The third will be postponed to a second vol ume. The first topic, then, is logic, or the theory of thought. The treatment will differ somewhat from that of the tra ditional formal logic, because thought itself is differently conceived. We agree with the traditional logician that logic cannot deal with particular and concrete objects of knowledge, but should confine itself to the general forms and principles of thought which apply to all objects. At the same time, however, we conceive that thought has many forms besides those of the notion, the judgment, and the inference. The entire system of categories belongs to the forms of thought, and must be treated in any adequate ex position. Furthermore, unless logic is to sink into a barren shuffling of artificial notions, without any significance for truth or knowledge, it must take some account of its own metaphysical presuppositions. A detailed and exhaustive discussion is not aimed at in the present work. The plan is rather to select such funda mental points for discussion as shall give the reader some idea of the essential nature of thought, and of the essential factors of the thought process. An insight into principles often dispenses with the discussion of details ; and the study of details without a knowledge of principles can come to no conclusion beyond barren reflections and desultory obser vations. CHAPTER I THE GENEEAL NATUEE OF THOUGHT TIIEEE is no fixed definition of logic. Accordingly, its field is extended all the way from formal reasoning to met aphysics, according to the pleasure of the speculator. Even those who agree in defining it as the science of thought do not agree as to the limits of thought, and thus the differ ence reappears. This is due to the organic nature of rea son, which forbids any hard and fast divisions. Hence, in stead of engaging in barren disputes concerning the exact limits of logic, it is better to recognize that those limits must always have something arbitrary in them, and to aim at consistency, relevance, and significance in our specula tions, whatever we call them. We define logic as the science of thought, and proceed to show what we mean by thought. Of course, our im mediate concern is with our human thinking. "Whether " Thought," or " Consciousness," or " Cosmic Thought " be a presupposition of our thinking must be postponed to the Theory of Knowledge. Meanwhile, we limit our attention to our human thinking. This limitation must be carefully noted, as oversight thereof has been a fruitful source of verbal disputes. It is plain that many things may be true for cosmic thought which are not true for our human thinking; and many limitations may be affirmed of the latter which must be denied of the former. The confusion of the two points of view can only result in further confusion. For the present, then, we occupy the human standpoint ; and our first work must be to gain some idea of what our human thought is. The life of consciousness, as occurring, is neither true nor false, but simply fact. Misconceptions are as much facts as correct conceptions, and arise equally in accordance with mental laws. But this life has another aspect, according to which it is not merely a mental event, but an apprehension of truth. In this respect it is also subject to laws which claim to be the laws of normal thinking and the conditions of reaching truth. The mental life, considered as fact, be longs to psychology ; the mental life, considered as appre hending truth, belongs to logic. This form of activity we call thought. Thought, then, is that form of mental activity whose aim. is truth or knowledge. The nature, laws, and implications of this activity a re the subject of our study. For the better understanding of this definition, it should be remembered that the term thought is often used with two entirely distinct meanings. Thought may signify the mental activity, and it may signify the contents grasped through that activity. In the latter sense, of course, thought includes everything which can exist for us. Sen sations, feelings, the whole universe, indeed, so far as it is known, belong to thought. From this point of view, thought has no antithesis, but is all-inclusive. Oversight of this ambiguity has been the source of not a little sterile and tedious logomachy, something like that resulting from con founding thought and " Thought." We have defined thought from the subjective standpoint as that form, of mental activity whose aim is truth or knowledge. The reality and peculiarity of thought as a special form of activity will further appear if we contrast it with the affections of sense. The human mind never rests in impressions of the sensi bility, but works them over into forms inherent in its own nature. In so doing it transcends the sense fact entirely, and it does this on its own warrant. Thus, suppose I am struck by a stone. The sense fact is simply certain visual, tactual, and painful sensations. If I say the stone hit me, I have transcended the sense experience, and attributed ob jective existence and causal efficiency to the stone. Sub tract these ideas, and there is nothing left but a succession of sensations in my own consciousness. Again, if I suppose I see a moving body, the sense fact is only a continuous set of visual appearances at adjacent points of space in successive moments of time. To trans form this into a moving body, I must pass from the fact of sense to the notion of an objective and identical thing. Or if I suppose I have successive experiences of the same thing, the sense fact is merely a similarity of successive sensa tions ; and I should never get beyond this, unless I inter preted the sense fact by the notion of an abiding and iden tical thing. Thus in these simplest and most elementary experiences we find a peculiar mental activity manifesting itself. There is a surplusage over the sensations. Here are ideas which are not sensations, nor any possible modifications of sensa tion. They do not admit of being sensuously presented, but belong to the unpicturable notions of intelligence. Yet the sensations become an intelligible object for us only as these ideas are superinduced upon them by the action of the understanding. This surplusage in experience beyond the contribution of the senses was recognized by Hume, and attributed to a mental "propensity to feign." There is, then, a great distinction between what is in sense and what is in thought. Of course, we at first sup pose that all those things are in sense which we perceive through sense ; but a small amount of reflection serves to dispel this illusion. In dealing with paintings and draw ings, or with printed and written matter, the eye gives only lines and colors ; the mind adds the meaning. But there can be no doubt that in all visual perception the meaning is contributed by the mind in like manner. What the eye gives is one thing ; what we see or perceive is quite another. Since the publication of Berkeley s New Theory of Vision this fact has been a commonplace of psychology. In hearing and the other senses the distinction is equally manifest. When we come to scientific study, the distinction between what is in sense and what is in thought is apparent even to the dullest. Even the sciences which have to do with physical objects live and move and have their being mainly in a world of rational conceptions which can be en tered only by thought. Very fe\v scientific conceptions admit of being sensuously presented or sensuously verified. Thus, along with the receptivity of sense, but distinct from it, we see a special order of mental activity which works over sense data into rational forms. From this point of view, thought might be defined as the process whereby the mind works over the raw material of the sensibility into the forms of intelligence. This would not be a complete defini tion, but it would call attention to one of the most impor tant aspects and functions of the thought activity in our ex perience. Once more we may illustrate the reality and peculiarity of the thought movement by contrasting it with the associ- ational movement. We find two orders of movement and combination in con sciousness. Man}?- things or events are found together or occur together in experience without any inner connection. But when they have thus come together in experience they tend thereafter to recur together by virtue of the laws of association. The most unlike things which have occurred together tend to recur together ; and sometimes the connec tion becomes so intimate as to seem a matter of course. Language furnishes a good example. The words, spoken or written, have absolutely no likeness to the thought, and no fitness to express just that thought rather than any other ; yet when once joined they seem to belong together, so that we even fancy we see or hear the thought itself. This fact underlies the order of reproduction. Memory reproduces the order of occurrence in accordance with the laws of asso ciation. This is the first order of movement. It is a me chanical grouping and reproduction of elements which have come together, and implies no internal connection. The second order is of a different kind. It aims to reach not accidental conjunction, but rational connection. The distinction between the two is that in the former case the elements only come together, whereas in the latter they belong together. Thus, sound and idea come together ; but the properties of a triangle, or cause and effect, belong together. The former might conceivably be separated ; the latter are fixed in changeless relations. Now, the second order of mental movement referred to aims to transform the occurrences and accidental conjunctions of experience into rational connections, so that our thought shall repre sent not merely the chance order of coming together, but the fixed order of belonging together. The associational order repeats indifferently the conjunctions of experience ; the thought order subjects them to a rational ideal. This antithesis between thought and sensation, or be tween the thought movement and the associational move ment, has not always been allowed. Thus, Hume recognized only conjunction and denied connection. In this he has generally been followed by the sensationalists. They have sought by means of association working upon sensations to evolve thought itself ; so that finally all that is native to the mind is the passive sensibility and the laws of as sociation. Given these, they aim to exhibit all else as product. In so far as this claim admits the present existence of laws of thought, it is irrelevant to our present purpose. It is an attempt not to deny those laws, but to explain them on a psychological basis. The laws are evolved but valid. The thought life roots, indeed, in the sense life, but has its special forms nevertheless. In so far as the associational claim contains a denial of the laws of thought, we shall consider it in connection with particular cases. We shall see hereafter that, if the antithesis of thought and sensation is to be denied, it must be from the side of thought rather than from that of sensation. It may turn out that sensa tion itself is in a very important sense a thought product. We come now to a point of the highest importance in studying the nature of thought. Eeference has already been made to it in speaking of thought as related to truth. Some amplification is in order here. Thought may be viewed as a mental event which ends in itself, and it may be viewed as apprehending or report ing a truth or reality beyond the mental event. Many of our conscious experiences are only mental events. They report nothing, and their whole duty is simply to be what they are. As such they are simply accidents of the indi vidual, and have no relation to truth. As Ferrier has it, they represent or apprehend nothing which is "common to all"; they are simply an experience which is "special to me." But the distinguishing mark of thought is that, in addi tion to being a mental event, it claims to represent a truth which is independent of the mental event. Of course, thinking, as a process, is particular ; and the entire contents of consciousness as mental events are particular; but our thoughts, though mental events, claim to be valid for an order of fact or reason which our thoughts do not make but discover, and which is common to all and not merely special to me. But there are some mental events which are only special to me, as feelings, moods, and all mental states which end in themselves ; yet in dealing with these the same fact comes out. For while these mental events are special to me in their occurrence, thought treats them as actual happenings in the total system of reality, and thus constitutes them a possible object of knowledge for all, and fixes them as actual components of the total reality. How thought can do this, how the particular thought which, as mental event, is special to me can nevertheless affirm and apprehend something valid for all is no doubt a great mystery ; but the fact is so involved in the nature of thought that thought vanishes altogether with its denial. It is this fact which constitutes the universality and objectivity of thought, and distinguishes the judgment at least, in its intention from a subjective union of ideas. Of course, this does not hinder that thought may often be mistaken. Chance conjunctions are put forward as fixed connections. Accidents of the individual are assumed to have universal validity. The special to me is mistaken for the common to all. But this very fact only illustrates once more that universality, or objective validity, is the essen tial form of thought. This conclusion finds further support in a consideration of the judgment. What does any judgment mean? It always involves the assumption of objective validity, and would be absurd or frivolous without it. Thus, suppose, for instance, that a geometrical judgment is in question say, the sum of the angles of a triangle is equal to two right angles. Xo one would admit that by this judgment he meant only that in his own consciousness the subject and predicate come together. Possibly, under polemical stress, a sensational philosopher might momen tarily take such a position ; and then the sufficient answer would be, Well, what of it ? The judgment being by hy pothesis an accident of the individual, no one else need con cern himself about it. But the bare fact of living together and of being mutually intelligible makes such a position impossible except as a verbal pretence. The geometrical judgment, then, carries with it a reference to a fixed order of reason which is common to all, and assumes to set forth some truth concerning that order. Or we may take a judgment in physics say, that water rises thirty-three feet in a pump under a certain barometric pressure. However many mental events may occur in reaching and announcing this judgment, no one would have the courage to say that it means only that certain notions cohere in his own consciousness. Even the most determined sensationalist or idealist would have to admit a world of coexistent minds and a universal order according to which all particular consciousness is determined. Without this admission the unlucky speculator would fall a prey to solipsism. Thus, the physical judgment contains a neces sary reference to an order of fact which is not an accident of the individual, but is common to all. The nature of this common fact may remain highly mysterious, but its exist ence cannot be questioned without absurdity. If, finally, we take an historical judgment say, Washing ton crossed the Delaware we see the same objective impli cation. Here an order of historical fact is assumed; and however necessary our thoughts as mental events may be for the grasping of the fact, they can never be identified with the fact. Thus, in the essential nature and intention of the judg ment, we see thought transcending itself as mental event, and positing a system for which our thought is valid, but which it does not make. The universality and community of the object have at bottom this meaning ; not that every one grasps it, but that the apprehending thought repro duces an order which is independent of itself. If it should occur to some one of idealistic tendencies to suggest that this objective system is itself only a thought, the answer would be that, if it were so, it could not be identified with the thought of the finite individual, but would be indepen dent of any and all of our thinking. For us, then, it would be something which we do not make but find. If, finally, any one should insist that thought cannot recognize any thing beyond itself, that might well be true for " Thought," but it is not true for our thinking. For, whether philoso phy can make anything of it or not, we are constantly recognizing an order of fact which we cannot view as de pendent on our thinking, or as vanishing when we go to sleep. This objective reference of thought is especially to be dwelt upon, as it is commonly overlooked by sensational ism and various cheap idealisms. They assume that im pressions are the raw material of knowledge, and that all that has to be done is to group the impressions. But they fail to make clear to themselves either the problem or the data of their own theory. Now, in strictness, the data are particular, unqualified impressions ; that is, they are im pressions of nobody by nothing. If we relax the strictness enough to allow the passive subject, then we have particu lar impressions in the consciousness of a particular individ ual ; and these admit of being variously associated. Then the problem is out of these data to generate the subjective form of knowledge and its objective validity. The insolubility of this problem is manifest as soon as we comprehend what is to be done. If we succeeded in generating the subjective form of thought from particular impressions, we should still have made no provision for the objective reference and objective validity. For associated impressions, after all, are only impressions associated, and remain accidents of the individual after association has done its best or worst. A solipsistic group of impressions is the only outcome ; and the judgment sinks into a men tal event which reports nothing. We are freed from these whimsies by remembering the objective reference implicit in thought from the beginning. But this affirmation of an objective reference in thought must not be mistaken for the claim that all parts of the thought process have their double in reality. Thought, the product, is objectively valid ; thought, the process, is no part of the object. Hence a double inquiry. This con cerns, first, the nature and laws of the thought process considered as a form of mental activity; and, secondly, the nature and extent of the validity of our thought for the independent object. In the latter part of the inquiry, logic passes into epistemology. Our immediate concern is with the thought process, its conditions and laws. The thought movement, when it becomes self-conscious and reflective, rises into freedom, in distinction from the me chanical movement of association. The thought life is rooted in our nature, and begins without our reflective volition. But this spontaneous thought remains on the surface of things, and needs to be rendered more profound and exact. This is the work of freedom. All earnest study, all science and philosophy, rest upon a will to know, and a direction of our powers to this end. Science and all the higher forms of knowledge are no mechanical product, but a free achieve ment of the truth-loving mind. Nature presents us with a few things in the mental life ; but only free work and devo tion can make us rulers over many. Thus, we have sought to show that within our experience there is a special order of mental* activity with law^s and aims of its own, which is to be distinguished from the mechanical order of association and from the passiveness of mere impres sibility. If in our further study we find reason for doubting this conclusion we promise to withdraw it. Pending such discovery, we pass to consider the general logical conditions of thought. thank you with love and a holy kiss blowing your way Roy Quote Link to comment Share on other sites More sharing options...
Recommended Posts
Join the conversation
You can post now and register later. If you have an account, sign in now to post with your account.